Philosophy and colors.

Заказать уникальный реферат
Тип работы: Реферат
Предмет: Английский начальный - средний
  • 25 25 страниц
  • 44 + 44 источника
  • Добавлена 29.05.2018
748 руб.
  • Содержание
  • Часть работы
  • Список литературы
  • Вопросы/Ответы
Contents
Introduction 3
1. The Philosophy of Color 3
2. The Aim of Philosophical Theories of Color 9
3. The Natural Concept of Color 13
Conclusion 23

Фрагмент для ознакомления

Some philosophers are invited to respond to this statement by saying that he raises a question against those theorists who believe that colors have hidden entities, for example physical microstructures. The control of this answer is that the idea that colors have hidden entities is not a correct theory about the natural concept or the people's concept of color. This can be plausible, as a theory of what is or should be a reformed concept of color, but not as a theory of what the people's concept is [3, 8, 17].
Admittedly, it's not easy to convince people of the presence of explicit properties. One of the problems is that many concepts begin their life as concepts of manifested properties, but then move into more complex concepts. We are talking about children's concepts of "horse", "dog", "man", etc. For them, the concept is almost exclusively determined by the corresponding occurrences. However, there are more complex examples. Take such concepts as brilliant, dazzling, cheerful, in a person, cheerful, gloomy, picturesque, gloomy, pale, etc. These are terms that characteristically relate to phenomena. All of these, we can assume, are explicit properties with the entities they wear on their faces, and are not hidden [29,32,35].
Many properties are not manifested: poisonous, created by the robot, containing water as an integral part coming from Virginia, etc., But some of them are clearly pronounced. These include colors. Someone who teaches color terms and understands how they are used knows what it has to be red for, be blue or some other: it must have that function that the perceiver is able to recognize. Reflecting on how colors are depicted, a thoughtful observer can say that the form of the colors of properties is represented as being, since colored "fillers" spread to the surface of physical bodies (or through volumes, etc.). They are inherent features of physical surfaces (volumes) that propagate over the surface. It is too clear that we feel the redness of a mature apple as an objective quality of an apple, reddening is in the objective space as well as the shape, contour, texture of the apple. This point can be accurately illustrated with quotations of two prominent workers in physiology / color psychology, Goering and Boynton. Goering, for example, writes: "When we open our eyes in a lit room, we see a variety of spatially extended forms that differentiate or separate from each other through differences in their colors. Colors - this is what fills out the outlines of these forms, this is the material from which visual phenomena are created; Our visual world consists entirely of different colors; and objects, from the point of view of their observation, that is, visible objects, are nothing other than colors of different kinds and forms "[16-19,32-34].
In the same vein, the physiological psychologist Robert Boynton writes in "Color in the contour and object perception": "From an early age, we can easily recognize the property of objects, usually associated with their surfaces, which we call color. relatively few adults, will doubt that the color is on (or sometimes in) the objects. " [4, 5] In addition, everyone knows about the different nature of how colors appear in different modes, for example, for surfaces of objects such as apples, light spots on screens, volumes such as wine, scattering media such as sky, light sources, such as globes, etc.
There is one more primary intuition, which is one of the most important. This is part of the people's concept, another "first-class intuition," that colors are presented as qualitative, sensual traits. This question will doubtless be controversial, but it should not be. The reference to the sensual nature of colors is crucial. These qualitative attributes, which are colors, are "sensual" in the broadest sense. This is not a problem of profound metaphysics. The term "sensual" is often used in such a way as to apply to a phenomenal, that is, ontologically subjective qualities. However, there is a wider meaning that does not have this obligation. For the term there is a neutral use. An illustration is an example that H.H. Price borrows from Husserl: "When I see a tomato hanging on a vine, then a ripe tomato, hanging on a vine": it is given to me with its sensual qualities" [38]. This sound is much better, of course, in German, but in English the point is that tomatoes (preferably still, grapes) and the vine are given in perception with sensual traits. The English understand that with the perception of tomatoes, grapes, etc. The person is familiar with sensual characteristics. Price recognized that regardless of the theory of perception, and especially, did you think that the perceiver is directly aware of physical objects or sensory representations; a person was familiar with sensory features.
A similar point is made by Evan Thompson [41], although with respect to the term "phenomenal", not "sensual". According to him, research in the field of psychophysics and visual physiology is limited to "phenomenal color structure." By this term, he means mainly three dimensions of color, known as shade, saturation and lightness, as well as relationships that colors manifest themselves. As he notes, textbooks often classify these properties of color as "subjective phenomena of color" or as signs of "color experience". Thompson prefers to use the term "phenomenal" to describe them, because they are, first of all, peculiarities of how colors appear: "Thus, I intend to use the term" phenomenal "in my older sense, referring to phenomena and not in the present sense subjective ".
Neutral concepts of "sensual" and "phenomenal" are those that can be shared by writers with very different philosophical obligations. This is the concept that Michael uses when he argues that when philosophers turn to the phenomenology of the perception of consciousness, by making claims to the phenomenal nature of experience, they mistakenly accept the intrinsic characteristics of the content of experience for the own characteristics of the experience itself,
Accordingly, we can represent writers as diverse as Price, Thompson and Tye [38, 41, 42], despite their philosophical differences, as in agreement. There is a neutral sense of "sensual" or "phenomenal", according to which physical objects can possess sensory or phenomenal properties. Most importantly, the color properties that the natural concept of color attributes to physical objects are sensory properties. Of course, a separate question is whether the physical objects have sensory functions, which they are represented as having. The price thinks they do not, but he also believes that another argument is needed to show that this is not the case.
In conclusion: taking into account the characteristic of the natural concept of color, color is a definite property. What kind of this can be indicated, in particular, that it is objective, perceiving-independent, explicit and sensual. In addition, the property is one with some kinds of cause-effect forces in relation to the representation of color in perception, recognition and identification of colors. Finally, colors are types of properties that are combined in the characteristic ways of forming structured color arrays with a characteristic three-dimensional character. They are properties that, as a group, form an internally bound structure of 4 + 2, built on four unique primary shades: green, red, blue and yellow and associated with a black and white pair. Some parts of this characteristic of the natural concept are controversial, for example, statements that colors are manifest and sensual. Some of the most significant parts of a characteristic that have the most far-reaching consequences are not contradictory: these colors have causal powers, as described above, and that collectively form a structured system.

Conclusion
It was argued that an adequate consideration of color should, first and foremost, ensure the consideration of the folk concept or the natural concept of color. Such an account, there is reason to believe, is an illusion of color theory. Suppose that colors, as we usually think of them, are virtual properties, we are faced with the question of how, if at all, we should adapt our ideas to colors. If our perception of color is usually associated with "false consciousnesses", what is the correct way to think about colors? The answer to this question is that for many purposes we must continue to think about them in the same way as always. In the case of color, unlike other cases, false consciousness should be the reason for celebration.
Although for most practical purposes it does not matter that colors are virtual properties, however, there are more theoretical purposes for which we need to develop a more complete account, pluralistic color information. Different elements of the natural color concept reflect the different functions that colors should play. Given these different functions and the fact that there is no property that satisfies all of them, we are open to developing a pluralistic framework in which different color concepts assume different functions. This pluralistic structure creates opportunities for the introduction of objectivist color concepts, but such concepts should stand side by side with the concept of a list of dispositions that refers to how colors are perceived by perceivers and, possibly, with the last phenomenal notion. This is the basis that is necessary to adequately take into account the rich epistemological and socially important roles played by colors.
Bibliography
1. Agoston, G. (1987), Color Theory and Application in Art and Design, Berlin: Springer.
2. Armstrong, D. M. (1969), ‘Color-Realism and the Argument from Microscopes’, Brown and Rollins (1969), Contemporary Philosophy in Australia, London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 119-31.
3. Berlin, B., and Kay, P. (1969), Basic Color Terms, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
4. Boynton, R.M. (1978), ‘Color in Contour and Object Perception’, in Carterette and Friedman, (eds.) (1978), Handbook of Perception, vol. 8, New York: Academic Press, pp. 173-98.
5. Boynton R.M. and Olson C.X. (1990), ‘Salience of chromatic basic color terms confirmed by three measures’, Vision Research, 30, 1311-17.
6. Broackes, Justin (1992), ‘The Autonomy of Color’, in Charles, David, and Lennon, Kathleen (eds.) (1992), Reduction, Explanation and Realism, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 421-66.
7. Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R., (1997), Readings on Color, Vol. I: The Philosophy of Color, Camb.Mass. : M.I.T Press.
8. Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R., (1997), Readings on Color, Vol. II: The Science of Color, Camb.Mass. : M.I.T Press.
9. Byrne, A. and Hilbert D. (2003), ‘Color Realism and Color Science', Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 26: 3-21.
10. Campbell, J. (1994), ‘A Simple View of Color’, in Haldane, John, and Wright, Crispin (eds.) (1994), Reality, Representation and Projection, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 257-69.
11. Campbell, Keith (1969), ‘Colors’, in Brown and Rollins (1969), Contemporary Philosophy in Australia, London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 132-57.
12. Cohen, Jonathan (2001), ‘Subjectivism, Physicalism, or None of the Above . . .’, Consciousness and Cognition, 10, pp. 94-104.
13. Evans, Gareth, (1980), ‘Things Without the Mind’, in Z. v Straaten, Philosophical Subjects, 10, pp. 76-116.
14. Hacker, P. M. S. (1987), Appearance and Reality, Oxford: Blackwell Publisher.
15. Hard, Anders, and Sivik, Lars (1981), ‘NCS-Natural Color System: A Swedish Standard for Color Notation’, Color Research and Application, 6, pp. 129-38.
16. Hardin, C. L. (1988/1993), Color for Philosophers, Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett.
17. Hardin C.L. & Maffi L. (1997), Color categories in thought and language, Cambridge: C.U.P.
18. Hardin, C.L. (2003), ‘A Reflectance Doth Not a Color Make', The Journal of Philosophy, 100: 191-202.
19. Hardin, C.L. (2004), ‘A Green Thought in a Green Shade', Harvard Review of Philosophy, XII, 29-39.
20. Hering, E. (1964), Outlines of a Theory of the Light Sense, trans. L. Hurvich and D. Jameson, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
21. Hilbert, D. R. (1987), Color and Color Perception, Stanford, Calif.: C.S.L.I.
22. Jackson Frank, (1996), ‘The Primary Quality View of Color’, Philosophical Perspectives, 10, pp. 199-219.
23. Jackson F. & Pargetter R., (1987), ‘An objectivist's guide to subjectivism about color’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 160, pp. 129-41.
24. Kaiser P.K. and Boynton R.M. (1996), Human Color Vision, (2nd edition) Washington: Optical Society of America.
25. Kuehni, R. (1997) Color New York: J. Wiley and Sons.
26. Land, E. H. (1983), ‘Recent Advances in Retinex Theory . . .’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 80, pp.5163-9.
27. Landesman, C. (1989), Color and Consciousness, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
28. Lewis, David, (1997), ‘Naming the Colors’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, pp. 325-42.
29. Matthen, M. (1988), ‘Biological Function and Perceptual Content', The Journal of Philosophy, 95: 5-27.
30. Matthen, M., (2000) ‘The Disunity of Color’, Philosophical Review, 108(1), pp. 47-84.
31. Matthen, M. (2005), Seeing, Doing and Knowing, Oxford: OUP.
32. Maund, J. B. (Barry) (1991), ‘The Nature of Color’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 8, pp. 253-63.
33. Maund, Barry (1995), Colors: Their Nature and Representation, Cambridge: Camb.University Press.
34. Maund, Barry (2006), ‘The Illusion Theory of Colour: An Anti-Realist Theory', Dialectica, 60: 245-68.
35. Mausfeld, R. and Heyer, D. (2003), (Eds.), Color Percepton: From Light to Object, New York: Oxford University Press.
36. McLaughlin, B. (2003), ‘The Place of Color in Nature’, in R.Mausfield and D.Heyer (2003)
37. Nassau, K. (1983), The Physics and Chemistry of Color, New York: Wiley.
38. Price H. H. (1932). Perception, London: Methuen.
39. Ross, P. (2001), ‘The location problem for color subjectivism’, Consciousness and Cognition, 10, pp. 42-58.
40. Stroud, B. (2000), The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Color, New York: Oxford University Press.
41. Thompson, Evan (1995), Color Vision, London: Routledge.
42. Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Color, and Content, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT/Bradford.
43. Van Brakel, J. (1993), ‘The Plasticity of Categories: The Case of Color’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,XL 44, pp. 103-35.
44. Westphal, Jonathan (1987), Color: A Philosophical Introduction, 1st ed., Oxford: Blackwell Publisher.






21

Bibliography
1. Agoston, G. (1987), Color Theory and Application in Art and Design, Berlin: Springer.
2. Armstrong, D. M. (1969), ‘Color-Realism and the Argument from Microscopes’, Brown and Rollins (1969), Contemporary Philosophy in Australia, London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 119-31.
3. Berlin, B., and Kay, P. (1969), Basic Color Terms, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
4. Boynton, R.M. (1978), ‘Color in Contour and Object Perception’, in Carterette and Friedman, (eds.) (1978), Handbook of Perception, vol. 8, New York: Academic Press, pp. 173-98.
5. Boynton R.M. and Olson C.X. (1990), ‘Salience of chromatic basic color terms confirmed by three measures’, Vision Research, 30, 1311-17.
6. Broackes, Justin (1992), ‘The Autonomy of Color’, in Charles, David, and Lennon, Kathleen (eds.) (1992), Reduction, Explanation and Realism, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 421-66.
7. Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R., (1997), Readings on Color, Vol. I: The Philosophy of Color, Camb.Mass. : M.I.T Press.
8. Byrne, Alex and Hilbert, David R., (1997), Readings on Color, Vol. II: The Science of Color, Camb.Mass. : M.I.T Press.
9. Byrne, A. and Hilbert D. (2003), ‘Color Realism and Color Science', Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 26: 3-21.
10. Campbell, J. (1994), ‘A Simple View of Color’, in Haldane, John, and Wright, Crispin (eds.) (1994), Reality, Representation and Projection, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 257-69.
11. Campbell, Keith (1969), ‘Colors’, in Brown and Rollins (1969), Contemporary Philosophy in Australia, London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 132-57.
12. Cohen, Jonathan (2001), ‘Subjectivism, Physicalism, or None of the Above . . .’, Consciousness and Cognition, 10, pp. 94-104.
13. Evans, Gareth, (1980), ‘Things Without the Mind’, in Z. v Straaten, Philosophical Subjects, 10, pp. 76-116.
14. Hacker, P. M. S. (1987), Appearance and Reality, Oxford: Blackwell Publisher.
15. Hard, Anders, and Sivik, Lars (1981), ‘NCS-Natural Color System: A Swedish Standard for Color Notation’, Color Research and Application, 6, pp. 129-38.
16. Hardin, C. L. (1988/1993), Color for Philosophers, Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett.
17. Hardin C.L. & Maffi L. (1997), Color categories in thought and language, Cambridge: C.U.P.
18. Hardin, C.L. (2003), ‘A Reflectance Doth Not a Color Make', The Journal of Philosophy, 100: 191-202.
19. Hardin, C.L. (2004), ‘A Green Thought in a Green Shade', Harvard Review of Philosophy, XII, 29-39.
20. Hering, E. (1964), Outlines of a Theory of the Light Sense, trans. L. Hurvich and D. Jameson, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
21. Hilbert, D. R. (1987), Color and Color Perception, Stanford, Calif.: C.S.L.I.
22. Jackson Frank, (1996), ‘The Primary Quality View of Color’, Philosophical Perspectives, 10, pp. 199-219.
23. Jackson F. & Pargetter R., (1987), ‘An objectivist's guide to subjectivism about color’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 160, pp. 129-41.
24. Kaiser P.K. and Boynton R.M. (1996), Human Color Vision, (2nd edition) Washington: Optical Society of America.
25. Kuehni, R. (1997) Color New York: J. Wiley and Sons.
26. Land, E. H. (1983), ‘Recent Advances in Retinex Theory . . .’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 80, pp.5163-9.
27. Landesman, C. (1989), Color and Consciousness, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
28. Lewis, David, (1997), ‘Naming the Colors’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, pp. 325-42.
29. Matthen, M. (1988), ‘Biological Function and Perceptual Content', The Journal of Philosophy, 95: 5-27.
30. Matthen, M., (2000) ‘The Disunity of Color’, Philosophical Review, 108(1), pp. 47-84.
31. Matthen, M. (2005), Seeing, Doing and Knowing, Oxford: OUP.
32. Maund, J. B. (Barry) (1991), ‘The Nature of Color’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 8, pp. 253-63.
33. Maund, Barry (1995), Colors: Their Nature and Representation, Cambridge: Camb.University Press.
34. Maund, Barry (2006), ‘The Illusion Theory of Colour: An Anti-Realist Theory', Dialectica, 60: 245-68.
35. Mausfeld, R. and Heyer, D. (2003), (Eds.), Color Percepton: From Light to Object, New York: Oxford University Press.
36. McLaughlin, B. (2003), ‘The Place of Color in Nature’, in R.Mausfield and D.Heyer (2003)
37. Nassau, K. (1983), The Physics and Chemistry of Color, New York: Wiley.
38. Price H. H. (1932). Perception, London: Methuen.
39. Ross, P. (2001), ‘The location problem for color subjectivism’, Consciousness and Cognition, 10, pp. 42-58.
40. Stroud, B. (2000), The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Color, New York: Oxford University Press.
41. Thompson, Evan (1995), Color Vision, London: Routledge.
42. Tye, M. (2000), Consciousness, Color, and Content, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT/Bradford.
43. Van Brakel, J. (1993), ‘The Plasticity of Categories: The Case of Color’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,XL 44, pp. 103-35.
44. Westphal, Jonathan (1987), Color: A Philosophical Introduction, 1st ed., Oxford: Blackwell Publisher.



Вопрос-ответ:

Какая связь между философией и цветами?

Философия цвета изучает сущность и природу цветов, а также влияние цветов на наше восприятие и понимание мира. Цвета имеют долгую историю в философии и открывают множество философских вопросов, связанных с понятием красоты, истинности и субъективности.

Какие теории о природе цвета предлагают философы?

Философы предлагают различные теории о природе цвета. Некоторые из них считают, что цвета имеют скрытые сущности, такие как физические микроструктуры, которые объясняют их восприятие. Другие философы считают, что цвета существуют только в нашем восприятии и не имеют объективной реальности. Есть также теории, которые связывают цвета с эмоциональными и психологическими состояниями.

Что такое "естественное понятие цвета"?

Естественное понятие цвета относится к нашему интуитивному пониманию цветов в повседневной жизни. Это то, как мы воспринимаем и называем цвета без философских теорий. Оно может отличаться от теоретических объяснений цветов, предлагаемых философами.

Какая теория о природе цвета считается правильной?

Философы не достигли единого мнения о правильной теории о природе цвета. Разные философы поддерживают различные подходы и трактуют цвета по-разному. Некоторые считают, что цвета имеют объективную реальность, другие считают их субъективными, и еще другие связывают цвета с культурным и социальным контекстом.

Как цвета влияют на наше восприятие мира?

Цвета играют важную роль в нашем восприятии мира. Они могут вызывать различные эмоции и настроение, а также влиять на наше восприятие пространства и форм. Например, яркие и насыщенные цвета могут вызывать чувство энергии и восторга, в то время как тусклые и холодные цвета могут создавать ощущение спокойствия и грусти.

Что такое философия цвета?

Философия цвета - это область философии, которая изучает природу цветов и их значение в контексте человеческого опыта и познания. Она исследует вопросы о том, как мы воспринимаем цвета, как они связаны с нашими эмоциями и субъективными впечатлениями. Философы цвета также исследуют философские проблемы, связанные с цветом, включая вопросы о существовании скрытых сущностей, отвечающих за цвета.

Какая цель у философских теорий о цвете?

Целью философских теорий о цвете является понимание природы цветов и их значение для нашего познания и восприятия мира. Философские теории о цвете стремятся объяснить, почему мы воспринимаем цвета так, как воспринимаем, и как цвета связаны с нашими эмоциями и субъективными впечатлениями. Они также исследуют вопросы о том, существуют ли скрытые сущности, отвечающие за цвета, или цвета существуют только в нашем сознании.

В чем заключается естественная концепция цвета?

Естественная концепция цвета предполагает, что цвета существуют независимо от нашего восприятия и субъективных впечатлений. Согласно этой концепции, цвета являются объективными качествами предметов и свойством света. Они могут быть описаны в терминах физических характеристик, таких как длина волны света. Естественная концепция цвета отличается от концепции, согласно которой цвета существуют только в нашем сознании и являются результатом нашего восприятия.

Какие аргументы есть против идеи о наличии скрытых сущностей, отвечающих за цвета?

Философы, отрицающие идею о наличии скрытых сущностей, отвечающих за цвета, приводят несколько аргументов в поддержку своей позиции. Они указывают на то, что объяснение цветов через физические микроструктуры не является удовлетворительным, так как физические свойства материалов не могут объяснить наши эмоциональные и субъективные впечатления от цветов. Они также подчеркивают, что наше восприятие цветов может изменяться в зависимости от контекста и обстоятельств, что предполагает, что цвета существуют только в нашем сознании.

Какие философы занимаются теориями о цветах?

Различные философы занимаются теориями о цветах. Например, в статье упоминаются философы, которые верят в существование скрытых сущностей цветов, такие как физические микроструктуры. Однако, есть и другие философы, которые не согласны с этой теорией и считают, что цвета имеют более естественное объяснение.

Какие вопросы возникают в философии о цветах?

В философии о цветах возникает множество интересных вопросов. Например, можно задаться вопросом, имеют ли цвета скрытые сущности, такие как физические микроструктуры, или же они имеют более естественное объяснение. Также возникает вопрос о том, как цвета воспринимаются людьми и как они влияют на наши мысли и эмоции. Все эти вопросы интересуют философов и ведут к различным теориям исследования цветов.

Каковы выводы автора статьи о философии и цветах?

Автор статьи предлагает рассмотреть возражение по поводу теории о скрытых сущностях цветов. Вывод автора состоит в том, что идея о том, что цвета имеют скрытые сущности, не является правильной теорией о естественном понятии цвета. Более естественное объяснение цветов может быть предложено, и это требует дальнейшего изучения и исследования философами. В статье не приводится окончательный вывод или ответ на этот вопрос, но она стимулирует к размышлению и обсуждению данной проблемы.